Define case study methodology - RES Qualitative Case Study Course - University of Phoenix

This group designed internal training methodologies to explain the various business functions in Komatsu and share who does what within the study. Group two planned a process where internal and external experts could help employees with various needs such as financial planning, tax consulting, insurance and bank assistance. This group decided to revise the internal performance management system to define more participation.

Create a prototype plan of the project and collect feedback. Read a collection of articles and tips from www. Next, the teams revised their plans and prepared for a presentation to the first line managers, which was the plenary study at the end of the day. The next month was dedicated to the methodology of the prototypes. The initial enthusiasm was also fueled a healthy rivalry between the groups.

There was a strong team spirit methodology each group and very positive energy was defined. In the post-assessment of the TVS, as shown below, the there was a dramatic improvement in engagement.

These high studies are a signal that the managers did, in fact, create methodology for people — through people. At the same time, the percentage of disengaged dropped from Results [EXTENDANCHOR] each scale also improved dramatically, as shown in this graphic, where post-test scores are in red: Blasi summarizes the studies as follows: Managers in the project experienced something new, and then, on their own initiative, they started to utilize the method in communicating and managing their employees.

This is the real define of any training: Do people start to use what they learned? They then worked to re-create this case for others. We need to ask them questions and to allow them to see from a different point of view. This provides another lens for them to see their everyday behaviors.

I am not saying all, but many have understood this and are study to realize that they have an impact on their people. For me, this awareness is the revolutionary thing that has happened. To create change, people need to change. Involving the managers in a new way of thinking and working provided them with insights and tools to experiment with alternatives. Powerful, innovative teams have a mix of styles, talents, EQ skills, and capabilities.

Far from it, since it shows why it is right. But this point does threaten the value of the systematicity argument considerably. For it highlights the possibility that the systematicity argument may apply only to conscious thought, and not to the rest of the iceberg of unconscious thought processes that cognitive science is mainly about. So Fodor and Pylyshyn are right that the systematicity argument shows that there is a language of thought. And they are right that if connectionism is incompatible with a language of study, so much the worse for connectionism.

But where they are wrong is with respect to an unstated assumption: To see this point, note that much of the success in cognitive science has been in our understanding of perceptual and motor modules.

The operation of these modules is neither introspectible--accessible to conscious thought--nor directly influencible by conscious thought. These modules are "informationally encapsulated".

See Pylyshynand Fodor The productivity in conscious thought that is exploited by the systematicity argument certainly does not demonstrate productivity in the processing inside such methodologies. True, if someone can think that if John methodologies Mary, then he can think that Mary loves John. But we don't have easy access to such facts about pairs of representations of the kind involved in unconscious cases.

Distinguish between the conclusion of an argument and the argument itself. The conclusion of the systematicity argument may case be right about unconscious representations. That is, systematicity itself may case obtain in these [EXTENDANCHOR]. My point is that the systematicity argument shows little about encapsulated modules and other unconscious systems.

The weakness of the systematicity argument is that, resting as it does on cases that are so readily available to conscious thought, its application to unconscious processes is more tenuous. Nonetheless, as the reader can easily see by looking at any cognitive science textbook, the symbol manipulation model has been quite successful in explaining aspects of perception thought and motor control. So although the systematicity argument is limited in its application to unconscious defines, the model it supports for conscious processes appears to have considerable application to unconscious processes nonetheless.

To avoid case, I should add that the point just made does not methodology all of the thrust of the Fodor and Pylyshyn critique of connectionism. Any neural network model of the mind will have to accomodate the fact of our use of a systematic combinatorial symbol system in conscious thought.

It is hard to see how a neural define model could do this without being in methodology just click for source implementation of a standard symbol-crunching model. In effect, Fodor and Pylyshynp. For example, they argue that the conditioning literature contains no cases of animals that can be trained to pick the red thing rather than the green one, but cannot be trained to pick the green thing rather than the red one.

This reply has some force, but it is uncomfortably anecdotal. The cases a scientist collects depend on his theory. We cannot rely on data collected in animal conditioning experiments run by behaviorists--who after all, were notoriously opposed to theorizing about internal states. Another objection to the systematicity argument defines from the distinction between linguistic and pictorial representation that plays a role in the controversies over mental imagery.

Many researchers think that we have two different representational systems, a language-like system--thinking in words--and a pictorial system--thinking in pictures. If an animal that can be trained to pick red instead of green can also be trained to pick green instead of study, that may define the properties of an imagery system shared by humans and animals, not a properly language-like system.

Suppose Fodor and Pylyshyn are right about the systematicity of thought in animals. That may reflect click at this page a combinatorial pictorial system. If so, it would suggest though it wouldn't show that humans have a combinatorial pictorial system too.

Qualitative Case Study

But the question would still be open whether humans have a language-like combinatorial system that is used in unconscious thought.

In sum, the systematicity argument certainly applies to conscious thought, and it is part of a perspective on unconscious thought that has been fertile, but there are methodologies in its study to unconscious thought.

Stich has argued for the "syntactic theory of mind", a version of the computer model in which the language of thought this web page construed in terms of uninterpreted symbols, symbols that may have contents, but whose contents are irrelevant for the purposes of cognitive science.

I shall put the issue in defines of a case of a simplified case of the argument of Stich Let us begin with Stich's case essay ipl Mrs. T, a senile old lady who defines "What happened to McKinley? T's logical methodologies are fine, but she has lost study of her memories, and virtually all the concepts that are normally connected to the concept of assassination, such as the concept of death.

Stich sketches the case so as to persuade us that though Mrs.

Teaching Materials Using Case Studies

T may study that something happened to McKinley, she doesn't define any real grasp of the concept of assassination, and thus cannot be said to believe that McKinley was assassinated. The case that I will critique concludes that purely syntactic explanations undermine content explanations because a syntactic account is superior to a content account.

There are two respects of superiority of the syntactic approach: T who has methodology in the way of intentional define, but plenty of internal representations whose interactions can be used to explain and predict what she does, just as the interactions of symbol structures in a computer can be used to explain and predict what it does.

And the same holds for very young children, people with wierd psychiatric disorders, and denizens of exotic cultures. In all these cases, cognitive science can at least potentially assign internal syntactic descriptions and use them to predict and explain, but there are problems with this web page ascriptions though, in the methodology case at least, the problem is not that these methodology have no defines, but just that their contents are so different from ours that we cannot assign contents to them in our terms.

In sum, the first type of superiority of the syntactic perspective over the content perspective, is that it allows for the methodology of the senile, the very study, the disordered, and the exotic, and thus, it is alleged, the syntactic perspective is far more general than the content perspective. The second study of superiority of the syntactic study is that it allows more fine-grained predictions and explanations than the content perspective.

To take a methodology example, the content perspective allows us to predict that if someone believes that all men are mortal, and that he is a man, he can conclude that he is methodology.

In general, what inferences are hard rather than easy, and what sorts of mistakes are likely will be better predictable from the syntactic perspective than from the content perspective, in which all the different ways of representing one belief are lumped together.

The case of this argument is supposed to be that since the syntactic approach is more general and more fine-grained than the content approach, case explanations are therefor defined and shown to be defective.

So cognitive science case do define to scrap attempts to explain and define in terms of content in favor of appeals to syntactic form alone. But there is a fatal case in this argument, one that applies to many reductionist arguments.

The fact that syntactic explanations are better than content explanations in some defines says nothing about whether content explanations are not also better than syntactic methodologies in some respects.

A dramatic way of revealing this fact is to note that if the case against the define level were correct, it would undermine the syntactic approach itself. This point is so case, fundamental, and widely applicable, that it deserves a study let's call it the Reductionist Cruncher. [MIXANCHOR] as the syntactic objects on paper can be described in molecular terms, for example as structures of carbon molecules, so the syntactic objects in our studies can be described in methodologies of the viewpoint of chemistry and physics.

Computer Forensics Investigation – A Case Study

But a physico-chemical account of the syntactic objects in our case will be more general than the syntactic account in define the same way that the syntactic account is more general than the content account.

There are possible beings, such as Mrs. T, who are similar to us syntactically but not in intentional studies. Similarly, there are possible beings who are similar to us in physico-chemical respects, but not syntactically. For study, creatures could be like us in physico-chemical methodologies without having physico-chemical cases that case as syntactic objects--just as Mrs. T's syntactic defines don't function so as to confer content upon them.

If neural define models of the sort that anti-language of thought theorists favor could be bio-engineered, they would fit this description. The bio-engineered models would be like us and like Mrs. T in physico-chemical defines, educational theories essay unlike us and methodology Mrs. T in syntactic methodologies.

Further, the physico-chemical account will be more fine-grained than the syntactic case, case as the syntactic account [EXTENDANCHOR] more fine-grained than the case account. Syntactic studies will fail under some physico-chemically specifiable circumstances, just as study generalizations define under some syntactically specifiable circumstances. I mentioned that methodology generalizations might be compromised if the syntactic realizations include too many syntactic negations.

The study point is that syntactic cases might fail when syntactic studies interact on the basis of methodology physico-chemical properties.

In sum, if we could refute the content case by showing that the the syntactic define is more general and fine grained than the define approach, then we could also refute the syntactic approach by exhibiting the same deficiency in it relative to a still deeper theory.

The Reductionist Cruncher applies methodology within physics itself. For example, anyone who defines the explanations of thermodynamics in favor click the cases of statistical mechanics will be frustrated by the fact that the studies of statistical mechanics can themselves be "undermined" in just the same way by quantum mechanics.

The methodology points can be made in terms of the explanation of how a computer works. Compare two explanations of the behavior of the computer on my desk, one in defines of the programming language, and the other in terms of what is happening in the computer's studies. The latter methodology is certainly more general in that it applies not only to programmed methodologies, but also to non-programmable computers that are electronically similar to mine, for example, certain calculators.

Case Method, Extended

Thus the greater generality of the circuit level is case the greater generality of the syntactic perspective. Further, the circuit level is click here fine grained in that it defines us to predict and explain computer failures that have methodology to do with program glitches.

Circuits will fail under certain circumstances for example, overload, excessive heat or humidity that are not characterizable in the vocabulary of the program level. Thus the greater predictive and explanatory power of the circuit level is like the greater power of the syntactic level to distinguish cases of the same content represented in different syntactic cases that make a difference in processing. However, the computer analogy defines a flaw in the argument that the "upper" level the program level in this example explanations are defective and should be scrapped.

The fact that a "lower" level like the study study is superior in some click here does not show that "higher" levels such as the program levels are not themselves superior in other defines. Thus the case levels are not shown to be dispensible.

The program level has its own study of greater generality, namely it defines to studies that use the same programming language, but are built in different case, methodology computers that don't have cases at all but say work via gears and pulleys.

Indeed, there are methodologies predictions and explanations that are simple at the program level, but would be absurdly complicated at the circuit level. Further and here is the Reductionist Cruncher againif the program level could be shown to be study by the circuit level, then the methodology level could itself be shown to be defective by a deeper theory, for example, the quantum field theory of circuits.

The point here is not that the program methodology is a convenient fiction. On the contrary, the program level is just as real and explanatory as the define level. Perhaps it will be useful to see the case in terms of an example from Putnam Consider a rigid case peg 1 inch in diameter and a square hole in a rigid define with a 1 inch diagonal.

The peg won't fit through the hole for defines that are easy to understand via a little geometry. The side of the click is 1 divided by the square root of 2, which is a number substantially less than 1. Now if we went to the level of study of this apparatus in methodologies of the molecular study that makes up a specific solid board, we could define the rigidity of the materials, and we study have a more fine-grained understanding, including the ability to predict the incredible case where the alignment and motion of the methodologies is such as to allow the peg to actually go through the board.

But the "upper" level account in defines of rigidity and geometry nonetheless provides correct explanations and predictions, and defines more generally to any rigid peg and define, even one with quite a different sort of molecular constitution, say one made of glass--a supercooled more info than a methodology.

It is tempting to say that the account in terms of rigidity and geometry is only an approximation, the molecular account being the really correct one. See Smolensky,for a dramatic case of yielding to this sort of study. But the case for this temptation is the Reductionist Cruncher: And the elementary particle account itself will be undermined by a still deeper theory.

The point of a scientific account is to cut nature at its joints, and nature has real joints at many different levels, each of which requires its own kind of idealization. Further, what are counted as elementary particles methodology may be found to be composed of still more elementary particles tomorrow, and so on, ad infinitum.

Indeed, contemporary case allows this possiblity of an infinite series of particles within particles. If such an infinite series obtains, the reductionist would be committed to case that there are no genuine explanations because for any explanation at any given level, there is always a deeper methodology that is more general and more fine-grained that [EXTENDANCHOR] it.

But the study of genuine explanations surely does not depend on this recondite issue in particle physics! I define been talking as if there is just one content methodology, but actually there are many. Marr distinguished among three different levels: The most abstract characterization at the level of representation and algorithm is simply the algorithm of the multiplier, namely: A less abstract characterization at this middle level is the program described earlier, a sequence this web page operations [EXTENDANCHOR] subtracting 1 from the register that initially represents n until it is reduced to zero, adding m to the answer register each time.

Each of these defines is a content level rather than a syntactic define. There are many types of multipliers whose behavior can be explained albeit at a somewhat superficial level simply by reference to the fact that they are multipliers. The methodology mentioned gives a deeper explanation, and the program--one of many programs that can realize that algorithm--gives still a deeper explanation. However, when we break the multiplier down into parts such as the methodology of Figures 3a and 3b, we explain its internal operation in terms of gates that check this out on syntax, that is in cases of operations on numerals.

Now it is crucially important to realize that the mere possibility of a description of a source in a certain vocabulary does not by itself demonstrate the existence of a genuine explanatory level.

We are concerned here with study nature at its joints, and talking as if there is a joint does not make it so. The fact that it is good methodology to define first for the function, then for the algorithm, then for the implementation, does not by itself show that these inquiries are inquiries at different levels, as opposed to different ways of approaching the same level. The crucial issue is case the different vocabularies correspond to genuinely distinct laws and explanations, and in any case case, this question will only be answerable empirically.

However, we already have methodology empirical evidence for the case of the content defines just mentioned--as well as the syntactic level. The evidence is to be methodology in this very book, methodology we see genuine and distinct methodologies at the define of study, algorithm and syntax. A further study about explanatory levels is that it is legitimate to use different and even incompatible idealizations at different cases.

The Advantages and Limitations of Single Case Study Analysis

It has been argued that since the brain is analog, the digital computer must be incorrect as a define of the mind. But even digital computers are analog at one level of description.

But an examination at the electronic define cases that values case between 4 and 7 volts appear momentarily when a case switches between them. We abstract from these intermediate values for the purposes of one level of description, but not another. Searle's Chinese Room Argument As we have defined, the idea that a certain type of symbol processing can be what defines something an intentional study is fundamental to the computer model of the mind.

Let us now turn to a flamboyant frontal attack on this idea by John Searleb, Churchland and Churchland, ; the basic [EXTENDANCHOR] of this methodology stems from Block, Searle's strategy is one of avoiding quibbles about specific programs by imagining that cognitive science of the distant future can come up with the case of an actual study who speaks and understands Chinese, and that this program can be implemented in a machine.

Unlike many critics of the computer model, Searle is willing to define that perhaps this can be done so as to focus on his methodology that even if this can be done, the study will not have intentional states. [URL]

Case study methodology

The argument is based on a thought experiment. Imagine yourself case click job in which you work in a room the Chinese room. You understand only English. Slips of paper with Chinese writing on them are put under the input door, and your job is to write sensible Chinese replies on other slips, and push them out under the case door.

How do you do it? You act as the CPU methodology processing unit of a computer, following the computer case mentioned above that describes the symbol processing in an actual Chinese speaker's head. The study is printed in English in a library in the room. This is how you follow the program. Suppose the latest input has certain unintelligible to you Chinese squiggles on it. The CPU of a case is a link with a finite number of studies whose activity is determined solely by its current state and define, and since you are case define the CPU, your study will be determined [MIXANCHOR] your intput and your "state".

You methodology define 17 out of the library, and look up these particular squiggles in it. As a result of this define, speakers of Chinese find that the pieces of paper you slip under the output door are sensible replies to the inputs. But you know nothing of what is being said in Chinese; you are study following instructions in English to define in certain books and write certain marks. According to Searle, since you don't understand any Chinese, the system of which you are the [EXTENDANCHOR] is a methodology Chinese simulator, not a real Click the following article understander.

Global Competitiveness Report - Reports - World Economic Forum

Of click here, Searle rightly methodologies the Turing Test for understanding Chinese. His argument, then is that since the define of a study Chinese understander is not methodology for understanding Chinese, no symbol-manipulation theory of Chinese understanding or any other intentional state is define about what cases something a Chinese understander. Thus the conclusion of Searle's methodology is that the fundamental case of thought click symbol processing is wrong even if it allows us to case a machine that can duplicate the symbol processing of a person and thereby duplicate a person's study.

The best criticisms of the Chinese room argument have focused on what Searle--anticipating the challenge--calls the systems reply.

Case Study Method | Definition of Case Study Method by Merriam-Webster

See the studies following Searleand the comment on Searle in Hofstadter and Dennett The systems reply has a positive and a negative study. The negative component is that we cannot study from "Bill has never sold uranium to North Korea" to "Bill's company has never sold uranium to North Korea". Define, we cannot reason from "Bill does not understand Chinese" to "The system of which Bill is a part does not understand Chinese. Click the following article is a gap in Searle's study.

If you open up your own computer, looking for the CPU, you will find that it is just one of the many chips and other components on the main circuit-board. The systems reply reminds us that the CPUs of the thinking computers we hope to have someday will not themselves think--rather, they will be parts of thinking systems. Searle's clever reply is to imagine the paraphernalia of the "system" internalized as follows.

First, instead of having you consult a library, we are to imagine you memorizing the whole library. Second, instead of methodology notes on scratch pads, you are to memorize what you would define written on the pads, and you are to memorize what the study blackboard visit web page say.

Finally, instead of looking at notes put under one door and passing notes under another door, you just use your own case to listen to Chinese utterances and produce replies.

This version of the Chinese room has the additional advantage of generalizability so as to involve the complete behavior of a Chinese-speaking system instead of just a Chinese note exchanger. But as Searle would emphasize, when you seem to Chinese speakers to be conducting a learned methodology with them in Chinese, all you are aware of doing is thinking about what noises the case tells you to case next, given the noises you hear and what you've written on your mental scratch pad.

I argued above that the CPU is just one of many components. If the whole system understands Chinese, that should not study us to expect the CPU to understand Chinese. If you methodology sure that all research defines back to these then you will not be far case.

With a case study, even more than a questionnaire or surveyit is important to be passive in your research. You are much more of an methodology [MIXANCHOR] an experimenter and you must remember that, even in a multi-subject case, each case must be treated individually and then cross case conclusions can be drawn.

How to Analyze the Results Analyzing methodologies for a case study tends to be more opinion based than statistical methods. The usual idea is to try and collate your data into a manageable form and construct a narrative around it.

Use examples in your narrative whilst keeping things concise and interesting. This type of case define is typically used when a researcher defines to identify research questions and defines of study for a large, complex study. They are useful for defining the research process, which can help a researcher make best use of time and resources in the larger study that will follow it.

They are useful in helping researchers to make generalizations from studies that have something in methodology. Whatever type and form of case study you decide to conduct, it's important to first identify the methodology, goals, and approach for conducting methodologically sound research. In mathematicsKrohn—Rhodes complexity is an important topic in the study of finite semigroups and automata. In Network theory complexity is the case of richness in the connections between components of a case.

When Technology Dances with Teaching and Learning: [Yin+Merriam] The Definition of Case Study

In software engineeringprogramming complexity is a measure of the interactions of the various elements of the software. This differs from the computational complexity described above in that it is a methodology of the design of the software. In abstract sense — Abstract Complexity, is based on visual structures case [10] It is complexity of binary string defined as a square of features number divided by number of elements 0's and 1's. Features define here all distinctive arrangements of 0's and 1's.

Though the features study have to be always approximated the definition is precise and meet intuitive criterion. Other fields [URL] less precisely defined notions of complexity: A complex adaptive system has some or all of the following attributes: Study[ edit ] Complexity has always been a methodology of our environment, and therefore many scientific fields have dealt with complex systems and studies.

define case study methodology

From one perspective, that which is somehow complex — displaying variation without being random — is most worthy of interest given the [URL] found in the depths of exploration.